top of page
Writer's picturePeace, Land, & Bread

Alienation, Falsity, and the Legitimation of Capitalist Society

BEN STAHNKE

 
"This conflict (within capitalist society) has the following form: on the one hand, the priorities set under economic imperatives cannot be allowed to depend upon a discursive formation of the public will—therefore politics today assumes the appearance of a technocracy. On the other hand, the exclusion of consequential practical questions from discussion by the depoliticized public becomes extremely difficult as a result of the long-term erosion of the cultural tradition which had regulated conduct and which, until now, could be presupposed as a tacit boundary condition of the political system. Because of this, a chronic need for legitimation is developing today." [1]
 

From where do our thoughts emerge? When we engage in linguistically-grounded thinking, are the ideas that we entertain original abstractions; or are they, as John Locke once suggested, directly informed by the social, material, and historical contexts of our lives? “External objects furnish the mind with the ideas of sensible qualities,” Locke noted, “which are all those different perceptions they produce in us.” [2] In other words, if we follow Locke on this, our engagement in the activity of thought requires that we must do so not only through the constraints of our physical structure, but also through the constraints and the entailments of our native languages, our socio-economic positions, and the historical pressures entailed by the polities to which we belong. Such constraints are, in essence, formative.


“Men make their own history,” Karl Marx observed, “but they do not make it as they please; they do not make it under self-selected circumstances, but under circumstances existing already, given and transmitted from the past.” [3] Marx went on to note, famously, that, “[t]he tradition of all dead generations weighs like a nightmare on the brains of the living.” [4] What Marx perceived here was that individuals within societies do not necessarily think and act in political and economic vacuums as discrete autonomous agents; they act, rather, as societies and in concert with a lengthy lineage of activity, thought, and discourse. Both history and the world itself thus shape our minds. And, as such, when we think linguistically, we can do so only in cooperation with the history of ideas, the lexicons, and the idea-structures which have been given to us by our antecedents.


In situ, there are, following the linguistic theories of Ludwig Wittgenstein (§243 - 256), no “private languages” apart from those shared within societies [5] and within the species at large. That our ideas emerge not only from the world itself, but from and in concert with our families, our societies, and our histories is, in part, the lesson of Plato’s Allegory of the Cave (§514 - 520), where “the prisoners would in every way believe that the truth is nothing other than the shadows of those artifacts” [6]; the artifacts, of course, being the shadows and the voices of our families and predecessors, as well as the shadows cast by those who deign to inform our thought. Thus, if we attempt to consider ourselves free agents, we can only consider ourselves free to act within the ideological and material constructs into which we have been born. While free, we are, as such, profoundly unfree. [7] But what if we are not only unfree in relationship to our material and historical circumstances, but also in relationship to a purposeful crafting of our ideological circumstances as well? Would Marx’s Bonapartian nightmare then not only emerge from the traditions of dead generations, but also from those of the living?


That we are, both in thought and in deed, a product of our times, our societies, and our geographies should be a fairly safe assertion. On this, the philosopher György Lukács once commented that: “As the products of historical evolution [societies] are involved in continuous change. But in addition they are also precisely in their objective structure the products of a definite historical epoch, namely capitalism.” [8] Capitalism—holding, as it does, an epochal political-economic hegemony over international materials exchange, production, and distribution—informs not only the objective structure of our societies but our thoughts which have been formed from our immersement in such societies as well. As a mode of production, [9] [10] and following the work of the political philosopher Louis Althusser, [11] capitalism must not only legitimate its material relations of production, it must reproduce itself ideologically if it is to survive a continually-critical, evolving, and emergent public—best represented by an abiding youth who seek, perpetually, to free themselves from the constraints of the past; futile as this may in fact be.


In the United States—the beating heart of the dictatorship of capital—ideological reproduction occurs by way of the influences of both state and social class over the internal discourses of politics, economy, populism, and iconography. Such a reproduction is not simply historical; it also takes shape through the purposeful ideation and action of living people. This is the crux and the open secret of political legitimation: that the formation and careful tending of our ideas about the society in which we live and participate is, for not only the U.S. but for every society, a crucial component of political existence. [12] A society will not long survive if its abstractive superstructure and the ideas of its constituents work against the internal cohesion of the state. In political science, this cohesion is known as legitimacy, [13] and the act by which polities sustain themselves ideologically is—not only through the Marxist lens, but the normative lens as well—known as legitimation. As an area of investigation, political legitimation is not a new topic of inquiry; rather, as the sociologist Morris Zelditch has observed, scholarship on legitimation dates back at least to the writings of Thucydides in 423 BCE. [14] On the unique phenomenon of legitimation under capitalism, however, the political philosopher Jürgen Habermas recognized that:


"Recoupling the economic to the political [...] creates an increased need for legitimation. The state apparatus no longer, as in liberal capitalism, merely secures the general conditions of production [...], but is now actively engaged in it. It must therefore—like the precapitalist state—be legitimated." [15]

That there is, intrinsically, something of a crisis in the modern-day legitimation of capitalism is not only an a priori political assertion; it can be aposteriorily evidenced by the great and historical lengths undertaken by the various apparatuses of the state in manufacturing legitimacy through direct manipulation, internal and external propagandizing, discourse hijacking, media scripting, and so on. Edward Herman and Noam Chomsky’s influential work, Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass Media, commented on this with the observation that the legitimating apparatuses, such as the mass media, in the United States "are effective and powerful ideological institutions that carry out a system-supportive propaganda function by reliance on market forces, internalized assumptions and self-censorship, and without significant overt coercion.” [16] In liberal-capitalist democracies—with their alleged Lockean emphases on individual freedoms and personal identities [17]—the endemic problematic elements of capitalism, such as poverty, exploitation, racism, social stratification, homelessness, and starvation must be explained-away through an all-out ideological assault on our minds: through the continual and long-term manufacturing of political, economic, social, and iconographic consents, as well as through the purposeful crafting of systemic excuses and intellectual discourses. Such a manufacturing of cohesive ideation—a forced legitimation—is the panem et circenses, or the bread and circuses of the great Juvenal who, in his Satires, lamented the shaking off of the “public [politically-involved] spirit” [18] in favor of the state-crafted spectacle.


Commenting on Habermas’s astute work on the legitimation crisis within contemporary capitalism—summed up as the conflict and contradictions between the decline of natural public acceptance and the increase of state-enforced legitimation tactics—the political philosopher Raymond Plant (F.K.C.) observed that:


"The problem posed by legitimation crisis is how the growing intervention of the state in economic activity can be rendered legitimate to those who are affected by the authority of the state in this sphere. The central question is: are there normative resources in society on which the state can draw to justify and sustain the degree of intervention required to avoid some of the dysfunctional effects of the economic market while at the same time securing the conditions necessary for the market to operate?" [19]

In other words, Plant here points to a pressing question not only for scholars of legitimation but for the constituents of capitalist society in general: by what avenues, and with what tools, might the so-called democratic state intervene to shape our ideas? Is it a leap in logic to assert that such resources, for the state, already exist?


One such example of this type of resource might lie bound up within the media organs of society—the traditional panem et circenses—which, to quote Herman and Chomsky, “[divert] the public from politics and [generate] a political apathy that is helpful to preservation of the status quo.” [20] Another example might lie in the overt intervention of the state within intellectual and scholarly discourse—an interesting instance of this being the Central Intelligence Agency (CIA) and the Office of Policy Coordination (OPC) [21] funding, during the 1950s, the Congress for Cultural Freedom [22]: a collective of allegedly left-leaning intellectuals and literary scholars dedicated to the publication of socialist journals, such as The New Leader, Der Monat, The Kenyon Review, The Paris Review, The Partisan Review, Encounter, Mundo Nuevo, and other such publications. [23]



There is an odd, yet not unexpected, logic at work in the cooption—and repressive tolerance [24]—of academic socialists operating as agents of state-sponsored anticommunism. This logic—the logic of weaponizing socialist theorists against existing communist-run states—continues to this day in the polemics of magazines such as Jacobin, where writers and theorists continue to polemicize against all existing forms of socialism except for the most utopian and western (read: white). The state tolerates, and in fact promotes, this type of socialist scholarship simply because it does not, at root, come anywhere close to harming the state itself or the state's property relations; the main target of these polemics are other anti-capitalists, anti-imperialists, and those engaged, most specifically, in real-world geopolitical struggles against the capitalist west. Such a tolerance appears at once both “weak and pleasant.” [25] And, further, it is incredibly effective when used as a tactic of internal legitimation against actual dissent. This is the true character of the Marcusian totalitarian democracy of capitalism: it is a toleration and cooption of all revolutionary ideas so long as they do not advocate, realistically, against the democratic state itself.


Writing on the Congress of Cultural Freedom, the CIA official and CNN co-host of the show Crossfire Thomas Braden wrote, in a 1967 article entitled, “I’m Glad the CIA is Immoral,” that:


"The fact, of course, is that in much of Europe in the 1950's, socialists, people who called themselves 'left'—the very people whom many Americans thought no better than Communists—were the only people who gave a damn about fighting Communism." [26]

The literary historian Allison Graham, in her 2001 book, Framing the South, touched upon the importance of iconography, film, and mass media in the crafting of public opinion, and indeed media’s power to “rewrite and even—literally—erase history altogether.” [27] What drives such iconographies, films, and examples are precisely the ideological components derived from the productive, distributive, and cultural structures of society itself. Yet these drivers are, following Graham’s analysis, not purely deterministic in nature. Rather, there in actu exists a dialectic of both determinism and malleability; such drivers holding the ability to be shaped by those who understand the mechanisms of shaping; an example of living ideas influencing living ideas; Plato’s puppeteers [28] come to life. And the puppeteers have been busy.


For evidence, we might look not only to the CIA’s Congress for Cultural Freedom, but toward the United States Central Command’s (CENTCOM) Operation Earnest Voice, [29] David Brock’s super-PAC Correct the Record, [30] The Smith-Mundt Modernization Act of 2012, [31] the restructuring of the Broadcasting Board of Governors (BBG) from a bipartisan nine-member board to a single, presidentially-appointed CEO, [32] Radio Free Europe/Radio Liberty, [33] Radio Free Asia, [34] the Middle East Broadcast Networks, [35] and pan-stational news scripting. [36] All of these seem to suggest that, to answer Raymond Plant’s earlier question about the potential avenues of existence for state-centered tools of legitimation, that such normative and legitimative resources already exist for the state. And, further, that these have always-already existed. [37]


That the engineering—as well as the resultant social alienation—of the ideas of the public occurs wholeheartedly and on a wide and insidious scale in the United States is not a new phenomenon, and was in fact argued for, publicly, as far back as 1952, where, in an issue of Fortune magazine, the Princeton-trained sociologist William Whyte asserted that:


"Only through social engineering i.e., applied groupthink—can [the public] be saved. The path to salvation, social engineers explain, lies in a trained elite that will benevolently manipulate us into group harmony." [38]

For Whyte, Groupthink—a term lifted from George Orwell’s lackluster and anti-communist opus, 1984—entailed a recognition that human societies tended to think together: “a rationalized conformity—an open, articulate philosophy which holds that group values are not only expedient but right and good as well.” [39] Here Whyte echoed, and hoped to exploit, an anthropological sentiment. He scoffed at naturalistic and unmodified groupthinking as “a perennial failing of mankind.” [40] An implicitly racist and colonial notion, Whyte's groupthink posited that societies could not, aside from the careful intercession of white capitalist nations, decide for themselves the best forms of society; the best social structures. For Whyte, the engineering of a “rationalized conformity” seemed to maintain for the Leviathan of capitalist society a Hobbesian salus populi, or “public safety,” where “the wealth and riches of all the particular members are the strength,” and where “civil war [is] death.” [41]


Groupthink sought to circumvent that Hobbesian tendency of a society to devour itself in lieu of reasoned, rational, and benevolent guidance. For Hobbes, however, it is important to remember that the utilization of language—whose general purpose was to “transfer our mental discourse into verbal” [42]—to deceive others was an “abuse of speech” between individuals; whereas it was expression of correcting and amending behavior [43] between government and the public. Where lying might represent a social sin between the individuals of a public, for both Hobbes and for Whyte, deception and lies were de rigueur of public statecraft.


Through the Marxist lens, however, this type of forced legitimation—groupthink applied by a dominant and exploitative élite—is not only inherently disingenuous; it is a purposeful, ideological alienation of the public from their own ideas, absent any sort of propagandistic forcing.


If we recall our opening notion that ideas themselves are necessarily informed by the social, material, and historical contexts from which they emerge, we might speculate that—in the absence of a forced, state-led legitimation—the extant material (and economically-exploitative) formations of capitalist society might cause an incumbent and unpropagandized public to delegitimate such a system by either political dissent or by revolutionary reaction. While, on the one hand, this might be a naïveté, it stands to reason, on the other, that continued state oppression would, and should, at some point, lead to the revolutionary uprising of the long-oppressed and exploited—exemplified and catalyzed by their lived existence in a capitalism in which a very small class of property owners and the ultra wealthy live in abject luxury off of the blood and sweat of the working poor: a working poor terrorized by the daily pressures of racist police, a lack of access to healthcare and mental health infrastructures, hunger, employment and housing precarity, widespread poverty, and the daily horrors of an untended and unmitigated pandemic.


We must give credit and agency to the poor and working class peoples; for the oppressed are only able to stomach their own historical oppression for so long. And the ideological and legitimative engagements of the state against the poor—and the lengths to which the state has gone, and continues to go—is a testament to the revolutionary potential of the class itself. The state and its ruling élite know that, in the absence of continual propagandizing, forced legitimation, and the manufacturing of consent, the days of their rule are numbered.


Thus, the subversive nature of the state’s sub rosa legitimative tools appear not only as aspects of an ideological apparatus but of an alienative and violent apparatus as well. In this light, the concept of political alienation becomes at once poignant and powerful. In one sense it implies the process and moment of estrangement from that to which we naturally belong; a disconnection from the fruits of our labors, from the world, from each other, and from our very essence as a species-being of the land [44]—a profound unfreedom whose articulation escapes us because we lack the very language by which to do so. [45] And, in another sense, it refers to a very real material process: the direct implantation of false concepts, a crafting of partisan economic discourse, a loss of control over the products of one’s own labor, as well as a reduction to meniality in regards to the process of labor itself—a debasement of man from free creature to one who must “perform uninteresting and degrading tasks.” [46]


Alienation, as an English-translative eliding of the dual philosophical concepts Entäusserung and Entfremdung—terms utilized by the philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel to signify a divestment of interest, or the act of estrangement, respectively—are endemic to the ideological legitimation of capitalism. [47] Alienation and legitimation are the two legs on which capitalist rule stands; they both result from and condone capitalist production itself. On this, the political scientist Bertell Ollman emphasized that, “The theory of alienation is the intellectual construct in which Marx displays the devastating effect of capitalist production on human beings, on their physical and mental states and on the social processes of which they are a part.” [48] Such devastating social effects only cut us off from that to which we must belong; they are a relinquishment of material interest in that towards which we should most naturally be interested: our physical and mental states suffering in a state of legitimated, crafted, and alienated repression of ideas. This is the true and robust nature of false consciousness under capitalism.


If we accept panem et circenses—bread and circuses—and state-crafted discourse in lieu of active involvement in the political process, and in lieu of a critical engagement with the ideas presented to us concerning social, political, and economic matters, we, as such, willingly submit to an alienation which is not only endemic to the present mode of production, we submit to an alienation enacted upon us by those who seek to profit from us—from our alienation and from our ideological repression. If purposive and repressive ideological conditionings are not confronted—if the war for hearts and minds is not confronted with reciprocal and stalwart purpose—and if, as Walter Benjamin suggested, we do not respond to such fascistic tendencies by “politicizing art” [49] and by politicizing the very nature of thinking itself, then we must admit that we allow others to tell us what to think; further, we allow others to tell us how to live, where such a living is against our better material and mental interests. Left unconfronted, we would thus allow not only a hijacking of our ideas, but a supplanting of false ideas—the creation of a false consciousness [50]— and “vaporous rhetoric” [51] as well. Left unconfronted, we must admit that, as our thoughts comprise our mind, our minds must also be false and unfounded things—that we, as allegedly free and democratic agents, are profoundly unfree precisely where it matters most.

 

ENDNOTES

[1] Habermas, Theory and Practice 5.

[2] Locke 323, emphasis added.

[3] Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte 2.

[4] Ibid. 2.

[5] Wittgenstein 98.

[6] Plato 187.

[7] Ibid. 188, §515e.

[8] Lukács 7. [9] Marx, Capital: Volume I 602. [10] A caveat lector must here be submitted that capitalism, following historian Michel Beaud in his A History of Capitalism, “cannot be reduced either to a mode of production, or to an economic system. And capitalism is not an actor capable of willing, planning, or choosing. At its heart, and through its various historical forms, transitions, and mutations, a complex social logic is at work. This logic is both structuring and destructuring, destructive and creative” (309). [11] Althusser 248.

[12] Kawachi and Berkman 174.

[13] Beetham 3. [14] Zelditch 33-53. [15] Legitimation Crisis 36.

[16] Herman and Chomsky 306. [17] Locke, “An Essay Concerning Human Understanding” 370.

[18] Juvenal 142.

[19] Plant 342, emphasis added.

[20] Herman and Chomsky xviii.

[21] The OPC is now the Clandestine Service, or the Directorate of Operations—an organ within the present-day CIA.

[24] “Universal toleration becomes questionable when its rationale no longer prevails, when tolerance is administered to manipulated and indoctrinated individuals who parrot, as their own, the opinion of their masters, for whom heteronomy has become autonomy” (Marcuse, A Critique of Pure Tolerance 90).

[25] Marcuse 6.

[26] Braden 11.

[27] Graham 17. [28] While some philosophers such as James Wilberding argue that politicians and legislators are ultimately the prisoners, and not the puppeteers, in Plato’s Cave; I take the view here that the inverse is indeed true. And, further, that there exists a dialectic between the prisoner and puppeteer.

[29] “The US military is developing [and utilizing] software that will let it secretly manipulate social media sites by using fake online personas to influence internet conversations and spread pro-American propaganda” (The Guardian 18 March 2011, Accessed 16 April 2018). [30] http://docquery.fec.gov/cgi-bin/fecimg/?C00578997 [31] https://www.congress.gov/bill/112th-congress/house-bill/5736/text [32] https://www.congress.gov/114/crpt/hrpt840/CRPT-114hrpt840.pdf [33] https://www.rferl.org [34] https://www.rfa.org/english/ [35] https://www.bbg.gov/networks/mbn/ [36] https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/02/business/media/sinclair-news-anchors-script.html

[37] Ricouer 57.

[38] Fortune 1952, emphasis added.

[39] Ibid. [40] Ibid. [41] Hobbes 115. [42] Ibid. 122.

[43] Ibid. 122.

[44] Marx, Rent of Land 116.

[45] Žižek 2. [46] Fromm viii.

[47] Entäusserung, in the language of the 1840s, and for both Hegel and for Marx, denoted a relinquishing of ownership. Entfremdung, in contrast, meant to be “cut off” (Chitty, emphasis added). [48] Ollman 131.

[49] Benjamin 49.

[50] Engels, “Letter to Franz Mehring.”

[51] Rosenbaum 387.

 

WORKS CITED


Althusser, Louis. On the Reproduction of Capitalism: Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses. Verso, 2014.

Beetham, David. The Legitimation of Power. Palgrave Macmillan, 2013.

Benjamin, Walter. The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction. Prism Key Press, 2010.

Braden, Thomas. “I’m Glad the CIA is Immoral.” The Saturday Evening Post, 20 May 1967, pp. 10-14, http://www.cambridgeclarion.org/press_cuttings/braden_20may1967.html. Accessed 14 April 2018.

CIA. “Origins of the Congress for Cultural Freedom, 1949-50.” CIA Library. https:// www.cia.gov/library/center-for-the-study-of-intelligence/csi-publications/csi-studies/ studies/95unclass/Warner.html, Accessed 16 April 2018.

Engels, Friedrich. “Letter to Franz Mehring.” https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/ 1893/letters/93_07_14.htm, Accessed 10 May 2018.

Fromm, Erich. “Foreword to Early Writings.Early Writings, Translated by T.B. Bottomore, McGraw-Hill, 1964.

Graham, Allison. Framing the South. Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003.

Habermas, Jürgen. Legitimation Crisis. Heinemann, 1976.

—-. Theory and Practice. Beacon, 1974.

Hennan, Edward, and Noam Chomsky. Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass Media. Pantheon, 1991.

Hobbes, Thomas. “Leviathan, Introduction, 1-5, 34, and 46.” Modern Philosophy: An Anthology of Primary Sources, edited by Roger Ariew and Eric Watkins, Hackett, 2009, pp. 114-136.

Iber, Patrick. “Literary Magazines for Socialists Funded by the CIA, Ranked.” The Awl, 24 August 2015, https://www.theawl.com/2015/08/literary-magazines-for-socialists-funded- by-the-cia-ranked/. Accessed 16 April 2018.

Juvenal. The Sixteen Satires of Juvenal: A New Translation, With an Introduction, a Running Analysis, and Brief Explanatory Notes, translated by S.H. Jeyes. Oxford, 1858, https:// ia902604.us.archive.org/22/items/sixteensatiresj00juvegoog/sixteensatiresj00juvegoog.pdf. Accessed on 26 April 2018.

Kawachi, Ichiro, and Lisa Berkman. "Social Cohesion, Social Capital, and Health." Social Epidemiology, 174 (2000): 190.

Locke, John. “Concerning Human Understanding I. 1-2, II. 1-14, 21-3, 27, III. 3, 6, and IV. 1-4, 10-1, 15-6.” Modern Philosophy: An Anthology of Primary Sources, edited by Roger Ariew and Eric Watkins, Hackett, 2009, pp. 316-422.

Lukács, Georg. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Translated by Rodney Livingstone, The MIT Press, 1985.

Marcuse, Herbert, Robert Paul Wolff, and Barrington Moore Jr. A Critique of Pure Tolerance.Beacon Press, 1965.

Marcuse, Herbert. "Repressive tolerance." 1965, http://ada.evergreen.edu/~arunc/texts/frankfurt/ marcuse/tolerance.pdf. Accessed 26 April 2018.

Marx, Karl. “Rent of Land.” Early Writings, Translated by T.B. Bottomore, McGraw-Hill, 1964. —-. The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte. International Publishers, 1994.


Ollman, Bertell. Alienation: Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society. Cambridge University Press, 1971.

Plant, Raymond. “Jürgen Habermas and the Idea of Legitimation Crisis.” European Journal of Political Research, no. 10, 1982, pp. 341-352.

Plato. Republic. Translated by G.M.A. Grube, Hackett, 1992.

Ricoeur, Paul. Time and Narrative, Vol. 1, translated by K. McLaughlin and D. Pellauer, Chicago–London, 1984.

Rosenbaum, Walter. Environmental Politics and Policy: Tenth Edition. CQ Press, 2017. Whyte, William. “Groupthink.” Fortune Magazine, 1952, http://fortune.com/2012/07/22/groupthink-fortune-1952/. Accessed 13 April 2018.

—-. “Groupthink.” Psychology Today Magazine, 1971, https://web.archive.org/web/20100401033524/

http://apps.olin.wustl.edu/faculty/macdonald/GroupThink.pdf. Accessed 13 April 2018.

Wilberding, James. “Prisoners and Puppeteers in the Cave.” http://ancphil.lsa.umich.edu/-/downloads/osap/27-Wilberding.pdf, Accessed 10 May 2018.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. Wiley-Blackwell, 2015.

Zelditch Jr., Morris. “Theories of Legitimacy.” The Psychology of Legitimacy: Emerging Perspectives on Ideology, Justice, and Intergroup Relations, Edited by John Jost and Brenda Major, Cambridge University Press, 2001, pp. 33–53.

Žižek, Slavoj. Welcome to the Desert of the Real: Five Essays on September 11 and Related Dates. Verso, 2002.

Comments


bottom of page